![]() |
Metamath
Proof Explorer Theorem List (p. 173 of 429) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > MPE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Color key: | ![]() (1-27903) |
![]() (27904-29428) |
![]() (29429-42879) |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | ipoval 17201* | Value of the inclusion poset. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 30-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐼 = (toInc‘𝐹) & ⊢ ≤ = {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ ({𝑥, 𝑦} ⊆ 𝐹 ∧ 𝑥 ⊆ 𝑦)} ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹 ∈ 𝑉 → 𝐼 = ({〈(Base‘ndx), 𝐹〉, 〈(TopSet‘ndx), (ordTop‘ ≤ )〉} ∪ {〈(le‘ndx), ≤ 〉, 〈(oc‘ndx), (𝑥 ∈ 𝐹 ↦ ∪ {𝑦 ∈ 𝐹 ∣ (𝑦 ∩ 𝑥) = ∅})〉})) | ||
Theorem | ipobas 17202 | Base set of the inclusion poset. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 30-Jan-2015.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 25-Oct-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐼 = (toInc‘𝐹) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹 ∈ 𝑉 → 𝐹 = (Base‘𝐼)) | ||
Theorem | ipolerval 17203* | Relation of the inclusion poset. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 30-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐼 = (toInc‘𝐹) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹 ∈ 𝑉 → {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ ({𝑥, 𝑦} ⊆ 𝐹 ∧ 𝑥 ⊆ 𝑦)} = (le‘𝐼)) | ||
Theorem | ipotset 17204 | Topology of the inclusion poset. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Oct-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐼 = (toInc‘𝐹) & ⊢ ≤ = (le‘𝐼) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹 ∈ 𝑉 → (ordTop‘ ≤ ) = (TopSet‘𝐼)) | ||
Theorem | ipole 17205 | Weak order condition of the inclusion poset. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 30-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐼 = (toInc‘𝐹) & ⊢ ≤ = (le‘𝐼) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐹 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝑋 ∈ 𝐹 ∧ 𝑌 ∈ 𝐹) → (𝑋 ≤ 𝑌 ↔ 𝑋 ⊆ 𝑌)) | ||
Theorem | ipolt 17206 | Strict order condition of the inclusion poset. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 30-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐼 = (toInc‘𝐹) & ⊢ < = (lt‘𝐼) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐹 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝑋 ∈ 𝐹 ∧ 𝑌 ∈ 𝐹) → (𝑋 < 𝑌 ↔ 𝑋 ⊊ 𝑌)) | ||
Theorem | ipopos 17207 | The inclusion poset on a family of sets is actually a poset. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 30-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐼 = (toInc‘𝐹) ⇒ ⊢ 𝐼 ∈ Poset | ||
Theorem | isipodrs 17208* | Condition for a family of sets to be directed by inclusion. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 2-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((toInc‘𝐴) ∈ Dirset ↔ (𝐴 ∈ V ∧ 𝐴 ≠ ∅ ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑧 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑥 ∪ 𝑦) ⊆ 𝑧)) | ||
Theorem | ipodrscl 17209 | Direction by inclusion as used here implies sethood. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 2-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((toInc‘𝐴) ∈ Dirset → 𝐴 ∈ V) | ||
Theorem | ipodrsfi 17210* | Finite upper bound property for directed collections of sets. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 2-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ (((toInc‘𝐴) ∈ Dirset ∧ 𝑋 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑋 ∈ Fin) → ∃𝑧 ∈ 𝐴 ∪ 𝑋 ⊆ 𝑧) | ||
Theorem | fpwipodrs 17211 | The finite subsets of any set are directed by inclusion. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 2-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (toInc‘(𝒫 𝐴 ∩ Fin)) ∈ Dirset) | ||
Theorem | ipodrsima 17212* | The monotone image of a directed set. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 2-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 Fn 𝒫 𝐴) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝑢 ⊆ 𝑣 ∧ 𝑣 ⊆ 𝐴)) → (𝐹‘𝑢) ⊆ (𝐹‘𝑣)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (toInc‘𝐵) ∈ Dirset) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ⊆ 𝒫 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐹 “ 𝐵) ∈ 𝑉) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (toInc‘(𝐹 “ 𝐵)) ∈ Dirset) | ||
Theorem | isacs3lem 17213* | An algebraic closure system satisfies isacs3 17221. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 2-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐶 ∈ (ACS‘𝑋) → (𝐶 ∈ (Moore‘𝑋) ∧ ∀𝑠 ∈ 𝒫 𝐶((toInc‘𝑠) ∈ Dirset → ∪ 𝑠 ∈ 𝐶))) | ||
Theorem | acsdrsel 17214 | An algebraic closure system contains all directed unions of closed sets. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 2-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐶 ∈ (ACS‘𝑋) ∧ 𝑌 ⊆ 𝐶 ∧ (toInc‘𝑌) ∈ Dirset) → ∪ 𝑌 ∈ 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | isacs4lem 17215* | In a closure system in which directed unions of closed sets are closed, closure commutes with directed unions. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 2-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (mrCls‘𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐶 ∈ (Moore‘𝑋) ∧ ∀𝑠 ∈ 𝒫 𝐶((toInc‘𝑠) ∈ Dirset → ∪ 𝑠 ∈ 𝐶)) → (𝐶 ∈ (Moore‘𝑋) ∧ ∀𝑡 ∈ 𝒫 𝒫 𝑋((toInc‘𝑡) ∈ Dirset → (𝐹‘∪ 𝑡) = ∪ (𝐹 “ 𝑡)))) | ||
Theorem | isacs5lem 17216* | If closure commutes with directed unions, then the closure of a set is the closure of its finite subsets. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 2-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (mrCls‘𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐶 ∈ (Moore‘𝑋) ∧ ∀𝑡 ∈ 𝒫 𝒫 𝑋((toInc‘𝑡) ∈ Dirset → (𝐹‘∪ 𝑡) = ∪ (𝐹 “ 𝑡))) → (𝐶 ∈ (Moore‘𝑋) ∧ ∀𝑠 ∈ 𝒫 𝑋(𝐹‘𝑠) = ∪ (𝐹 “ (𝒫 𝑠 ∩ Fin)))) | ||
Theorem | acsdrscl 17217 | In an algebraic closure system, closure commutes with directed unions. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 2-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (mrCls‘𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐶 ∈ (ACS‘𝑋) ∧ 𝑌 ⊆ 𝒫 𝑋 ∧ (toInc‘𝑌) ∈ Dirset) → (𝐹‘∪ 𝑌) = ∪ (𝐹 “ 𝑌)) | ||
Theorem | acsficl 17218 | A closure in an algebraic closure system is the union of the closures of finite subsets. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 2-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (mrCls‘𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐶 ∈ (ACS‘𝑋) ∧ 𝑆 ⊆ 𝑋) → (𝐹‘𝑆) = ∪ (𝐹 “ (𝒫 𝑆 ∩ Fin))) | ||
Theorem | isacs5 17219* | A closure system is algebraic iff the closure of a generating set is the union of the closures of its finite subsets. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 2-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (mrCls‘𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐶 ∈ (ACS‘𝑋) ↔ (𝐶 ∈ (Moore‘𝑋) ∧ ∀𝑠 ∈ 𝒫 𝑋(𝐹‘𝑠) = ∪ (𝐹 “ (𝒫 𝑠 ∩ Fin)))) | ||
Theorem | isacs4 17220* | A closure system is algebraic iff closure commutes with directed unions. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 2-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (mrCls‘𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐶 ∈ (ACS‘𝑋) ↔ (𝐶 ∈ (Moore‘𝑋) ∧ ∀𝑠 ∈ 𝒫 𝒫 𝑋((toInc‘𝑠) ∈ Dirset → (𝐹‘∪ 𝑠) = ∪ (𝐹 “ 𝑠)))) | ||
Theorem | isacs3 17221* | A closure system is algebraic iff directed unions of closed sets are closed. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 2-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐶 ∈ (ACS‘𝑋) ↔ (𝐶 ∈ (Moore‘𝑋) ∧ ∀𝑠 ∈ 𝒫 𝐶((toInc‘𝑠) ∈ Dirset → ∪ 𝑠 ∈ 𝐶))) | ||
Theorem | acsficld 17222 | In an algebraic closure system, the closure of a set is the union of the closures of its finite subsets. Deduction form of acsficl 17218. (Contributed by David Moews, 1-May-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ (ACS‘𝑋)) & ⊢ 𝑁 = (mrCls‘𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 ⊆ 𝑋) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑁‘𝑆) = ∪ (𝑁 “ (𝒫 𝑆 ∩ Fin))) | ||
Theorem | acsficl2d 17223* | In an algebraic closure system, an element is in the closure of a set if and only if it is in the closure of a finite subset. Alternate form of acsficl 17218. Deduction form. (Contributed by David Moews, 1-May-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ (ACS‘𝑋)) & ⊢ 𝑁 = (mrCls‘𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 ⊆ 𝑋) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑌 ∈ (𝑁‘𝑆) ↔ ∃𝑥 ∈ (𝒫 𝑆 ∩ Fin)𝑌 ∈ (𝑁‘𝑥))) | ||
Theorem | acsfiindd 17224 | In an algebraic closure system, a set is independent if and only if all its finite subsets are independent. Part of Proposition 4.1.3 in [FaureFrolicher] p. 83. (Contributed by David Moews, 1-May-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ (ACS‘𝑋)) & ⊢ 𝑁 = (mrCls‘𝐴) & ⊢ 𝐼 = (mrInd‘𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 ⊆ 𝑋) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑆 ∈ 𝐼 ↔ (𝒫 𝑆 ∩ Fin) ⊆ 𝐼)) | ||
Theorem | acsmapd 17225* | In an algebraic closure system, if 𝑇 is contained in the closure of 𝑆, there is a map 𝑓 from 𝑇 into the set of finite subsets of 𝑆 such that the closure of ∪ ran 𝑓 contains 𝑇. This is proven by applying acsficl2d 17223 to each element of 𝑇. See Section II.5 in [Cohn] p. 81 to 82. (Contributed by David Moews, 1-May-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ (ACS‘𝑋)) & ⊢ 𝑁 = (mrCls‘𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 ⊆ 𝑋) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 ⊆ (𝑁‘𝑆)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑓(𝑓:𝑇⟶(𝒫 𝑆 ∩ Fin) ∧ 𝑇 ⊆ (𝑁‘∪ ran 𝑓))) | ||
Theorem | acsmap2d 17226* | In an algebraic closure system, if 𝑆 and 𝑇 have the same closure and 𝑆 is independent, then there is a map 𝑓 from 𝑇 into the set of finite subsets of 𝑆 such that 𝑆 equals the union of ran 𝑓. This is proven by taking the map 𝑓 from acsmapd 17225 and observing that, since 𝑆 and 𝑇 have the same closure, the closure of ∪ ran 𝑓 must contain 𝑆. Since 𝑆 is independent, by mrissmrcd 16347, ∪ ran 𝑓 must equal 𝑆. See Section II.5 in [Cohn] p. 81 to 82. (Contributed by David Moews, 1-May-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ (ACS‘𝑋)) & ⊢ 𝑁 = (mrCls‘𝐴) & ⊢ 𝐼 = (mrInd‘𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 ∈ 𝐼) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 ⊆ 𝑋) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑁‘𝑆) = (𝑁‘𝑇)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑓(𝑓:𝑇⟶(𝒫 𝑆 ∩ Fin) ∧ 𝑆 = ∪ ran 𝑓)) | ||
Theorem | acsinfd 17227 | In an algebraic closure system, if 𝑆 and 𝑇 have the same closure and 𝑆 is infinite independent, then 𝑇 is infinite. This follows from applying unirnffid 8299 to the map given in acsmap2d 17226. See Section II.5 in [Cohn] p. 81 to 82. (Contributed by David Moews, 1-May-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ (ACS‘𝑋)) & ⊢ 𝑁 = (mrCls‘𝐴) & ⊢ 𝐼 = (mrInd‘𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 ∈ 𝐼) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 ⊆ 𝑋) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑁‘𝑆) = (𝑁‘𝑇)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝑆 ∈ Fin) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝑇 ∈ Fin) | ||
Theorem | acsdomd 17228 | In an algebraic closure system, if 𝑆 and 𝑇 have the same closure and 𝑆 is infinite independent, then 𝑇 dominates 𝑆. This follows from applying acsinfd 17227 and then applying unirnfdomd 9427 to the map given in acsmap2d 17226. See Section II.5 in [Cohn] p. 81 to 82. (Contributed by David Moews, 1-May-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ (ACS‘𝑋)) & ⊢ 𝑁 = (mrCls‘𝐴) & ⊢ 𝐼 = (mrInd‘𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 ∈ 𝐼) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 ⊆ 𝑋) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑁‘𝑆) = (𝑁‘𝑇)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝑆 ∈ Fin) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 ≼ 𝑇) | ||
Theorem | acsinfdimd 17229 | In an algebraic closure system, if two independent sets have equal closure and one is infinite, then they are equinumerous. This is proven by using acsdomd 17228 twice with acsinfd 17227. See Section II.5 in [Cohn] p. 81 to 82. (Contributed by David Moews, 1-May-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ (ACS‘𝑋)) & ⊢ 𝑁 = (mrCls‘𝐴) & ⊢ 𝐼 = (mrInd‘𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 ∈ 𝐼) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 ∈ 𝐼) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑁‘𝑆) = (𝑁‘𝑇)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝑆 ∈ Fin) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 ≈ 𝑇) | ||
Theorem | acsexdimd 17230* | In an algebraic closure system whose closure operator has the exchange property, if two independent sets have equal closure, they are equinumerous. See mreexfidimd 16358 for the finite case and acsinfdimd 17229 for the infinite case. This is a special case of Theorem 4.2.2 in [FaureFrolicher] p. 87. (Contributed by David Moews, 1-May-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ (ACS‘𝑋)) & ⊢ 𝑁 = (mrCls‘𝐴) & ⊢ 𝐼 = (mrInd‘𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑠 ∈ 𝒫 𝑋∀𝑦 ∈ 𝑋 ∀𝑧 ∈ ((𝑁‘(𝑠 ∪ {𝑦})) ∖ (𝑁‘𝑠))𝑦 ∈ (𝑁‘(𝑠 ∪ {𝑧}))) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 ∈ 𝐼) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 ∈ 𝐼) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑁‘𝑆) = (𝑁‘𝑇)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 ≈ 𝑇) | ||
Theorem | mrelatglb 17231 | Greatest lower bounds in a Moore space are realized by intersections. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 31-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐼 = (toInc‘𝐶) & ⊢ 𝐺 = (glb‘𝐼) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐶 ∈ (Moore‘𝑋) ∧ 𝑈 ⊆ 𝐶 ∧ 𝑈 ≠ ∅) → (𝐺‘𝑈) = ∩ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | mrelatglb0 17232 | The empty intersection in a Moore space is realized by the base set. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 31-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐼 = (toInc‘𝐶) & ⊢ 𝐺 = (glb‘𝐼) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐶 ∈ (Moore‘𝑋) → (𝐺‘∅) = 𝑋) | ||
Theorem | mrelatlub 17233 | Least upper bounds in a Moore space are realized by the closure of the union. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 31-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐼 = (toInc‘𝐶) & ⊢ 𝐹 = (mrCls‘𝐶) & ⊢ 𝐿 = (lub‘𝐼) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐶 ∈ (Moore‘𝑋) ∧ 𝑈 ⊆ 𝐶) → (𝐿‘𝑈) = (𝐹‘∪ 𝑈)) | ||
Theorem | mreclatBAD 17234* | A Moore space is a complete lattice under inclusion. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 31-Jan-2015.) TODO (df-riota 6651 update): Reprove using isclat 17156 instead of the isclatBAD. hypothesis. See commented-out mreclat above. |
⊢ 𝐼 = (toInc‘𝐶) & ⊢ (𝐼 ∈ CLat ↔ (𝐼 ∈ Poset ∧ ∀𝑥(𝑥 ⊆ (Base‘𝐼) → (((lub‘𝐼)‘𝑥) ∈ (Base‘𝐼) ∧ ((glb‘𝐼)‘𝑥) ∈ (Base‘𝐼))))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐶 ∈ (Moore‘𝑋) → 𝐼 ∈ CLat) | ||
Theorem | latmass 17235 | Lattice meet is associative. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 30-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐵 = (Base‘𝐾) & ⊢ ∧ = (meet‘𝐾) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐾 ∈ Lat ∧ (𝑋 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝑌 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝑍 ∈ 𝐵)) → ((𝑋 ∧ 𝑌) ∧ 𝑍) = (𝑋 ∧ (𝑌 ∧ 𝑍))) | ||
Theorem | latdisdlem 17236* | Lemma for latdisd 17237. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 30-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐵 = (Base‘𝐾) & ⊢ ∨ = (join‘𝐾) & ⊢ ∧ = (meet‘𝐾) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐾 ∈ Lat → (∀𝑢 ∈ 𝐵 ∀𝑣 ∈ 𝐵 ∀𝑤 ∈ 𝐵 (𝑢 ∨ (𝑣 ∧ 𝑤)) = ((𝑢 ∨ 𝑣) ∧ (𝑢 ∨ 𝑤)) → ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝐵 (𝑥 ∧ (𝑦 ∨ 𝑧)) = ((𝑥 ∧ 𝑦) ∨ (𝑥 ∧ 𝑧)))) | ||
Theorem | latdisd 17237* | In a lattice, joins distribute over meets if and only if meets distribute over joins; the distributive property is self-dual. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 29-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐵 = (Base‘𝐾) & ⊢ ∨ = (join‘𝐾) & ⊢ ∧ = (meet‘𝐾) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐾 ∈ Lat → (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝐵 (𝑥 ∨ (𝑦 ∧ 𝑧)) = ((𝑥 ∨ 𝑦) ∧ (𝑥 ∨ 𝑧)) ↔ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝐵 (𝑥 ∧ (𝑦 ∨ 𝑧)) = ((𝑥 ∧ 𝑦) ∨ (𝑥 ∧ 𝑧)))) | ||
Syntax | cdlat 17238 | The class of distributive lattices. |
class DLat | ||
Definition | df-dlat 17239* | A distributive lattice is a lattice in which meets distribute over joins, or equivalently (latdisd 17237) joins distribute over meets. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 30-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ DLat = {𝑘 ∈ Lat ∣ [(Base‘𝑘) / 𝑏][(join‘𝑘) / 𝑗][(meet‘𝑘) / 𝑚]∀𝑥 ∈ 𝑏 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝑏 ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑏 (𝑥𝑚(𝑦𝑗𝑧)) = ((𝑥𝑚𝑦)𝑗(𝑥𝑚𝑧))} | ||
Theorem | isdlat 17240* | Property of being a distributive lattice. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 30-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐵 = (Base‘𝐾) & ⊢ ∨ = (join‘𝐾) & ⊢ ∧ = (meet‘𝐾) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐾 ∈ DLat ↔ (𝐾 ∈ Lat ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝐵 (𝑥 ∧ (𝑦 ∨ 𝑧)) = ((𝑥 ∧ 𝑦) ∨ (𝑥 ∧ 𝑧)))) | ||
Theorem | dlatmjdi 17241 | In a distributive lattice, meets distribute over joins. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 30-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐵 = (Base‘𝐾) & ⊢ ∨ = (join‘𝐾) & ⊢ ∧ = (meet‘𝐾) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐾 ∈ DLat ∧ (𝑋 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝑌 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝑍 ∈ 𝐵)) → (𝑋 ∧ (𝑌 ∨ 𝑍)) = ((𝑋 ∧ 𝑌) ∨ (𝑋 ∧ 𝑍))) | ||
Theorem | dlatl 17242 | A distributive lattice is a lattice. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 30-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐾 ∈ DLat → 𝐾 ∈ Lat) | ||
Theorem | odudlatb 17243 | The dual of a distributive lattice is a distributive lattice and conversely. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 30-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐷 = (ODual‘𝐾) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐾 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐾 ∈ DLat ↔ 𝐷 ∈ DLat)) | ||
Theorem | dlatjmdi 17244 | In a distributive lattice, joins distribute over meets. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 30-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐵 = (Base‘𝐾) & ⊢ ∨ = (join‘𝐾) & ⊢ ∧ = (meet‘𝐾) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐾 ∈ DLat ∧ (𝑋 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝑌 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝑍 ∈ 𝐵)) → (𝑋 ∨ (𝑌 ∧ 𝑍)) = ((𝑋 ∨ 𝑌) ∧ (𝑋 ∨ 𝑍))) | ||
Syntax | cps 17245 | Extend class notation with the class of all posets. |
class PosetRel | ||
Syntax | ctsr 17246 | Extend class notation with the class of all totally ordered sets. |
class TosetRel | ||
Definition | df-ps 17247 | Define the class of all posets (partially ordered sets) with weak ordering (e.g., "less than or equal to" instead of "less than"). A poset is a relation which is transitive, reflexive, and antisymmetric. (Contributed by NM, 11-May-2008.) |
⊢ PosetRel = {𝑟 ∣ (Rel 𝑟 ∧ (𝑟 ∘ 𝑟) ⊆ 𝑟 ∧ (𝑟 ∩ ◡𝑟) = ( I ↾ ∪ ∪ 𝑟))} | ||
Definition | df-tsr 17248 | Define the class of all totally ordered sets. (Contributed by FL, 1-Nov-2009.) |
⊢ TosetRel = {𝑟 ∈ PosetRel ∣ (dom 𝑟 × dom 𝑟) ⊆ (𝑟 ∪ ◡𝑟)} | ||
Theorem | isps 17249 | The predicate "is a poset" i.e. a transitive, reflexive, antisymmetric relation. (Contributed by NM, 11-May-2008.) |
⊢ (𝑅 ∈ 𝐴 → (𝑅 ∈ PosetRel ↔ (Rel 𝑅 ∧ (𝑅 ∘ 𝑅) ⊆ 𝑅 ∧ (𝑅 ∩ ◡𝑅) = ( I ↾ ∪ ∪ 𝑅)))) | ||
Theorem | psrel 17250 | A poset is a relation. (Contributed by NM, 12-May-2008.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ PosetRel → Rel 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | psref2 17251 | A poset is antisymmetric and reflexive. (Contributed by FL, 3-Aug-2009.) |
⊢ (𝑅 ∈ PosetRel → (𝑅 ∩ ◡𝑅) = ( I ↾ ∪ ∪ 𝑅)) | ||
Theorem | pstr2 17252 | A poset is transitive. (Contributed by FL, 3-Aug-2009.) |
⊢ (𝑅 ∈ PosetRel → (𝑅 ∘ 𝑅) ⊆ 𝑅) | ||
Theorem | pslem 17253 | Lemma for psref 17255 and others. (Contributed by NM, 12-May-2008.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 30-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑅 ∈ PosetRel → (((𝐴𝑅𝐵 ∧ 𝐵𝑅𝐶) → 𝐴𝑅𝐶) ∧ (𝐴 ∈ ∪ ∪ 𝑅 → 𝐴𝑅𝐴) ∧ ((𝐴𝑅𝐵 ∧ 𝐵𝑅𝐴) → 𝐴 = 𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | psdmrn 17254 | The domain and range of a poset equal its field. (Contributed by NM, 13-May-2008.) |
⊢ (𝑅 ∈ PosetRel → (dom 𝑅 = ∪ ∪ 𝑅 ∧ ran 𝑅 = ∪ ∪ 𝑅)) | ||
Theorem | psref 17255 | A poset is reflexive. (Contributed by NM, 13-May-2008.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = dom 𝑅 ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑅 ∈ PosetRel ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑋) → 𝐴𝑅𝐴) | ||
Theorem | psrn 17256 | The range of a poset equals it domain. (Contributed by NM, 7-Jul-2008.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = dom 𝑅 ⇒ ⊢ (𝑅 ∈ PosetRel → 𝑋 = ran 𝑅) | ||
Theorem | psasym 17257 | A poset is antisymmetric. (Contributed by NM, 12-May-2008.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 ∈ PosetRel ∧ 𝐴𝑅𝐵 ∧ 𝐵𝑅𝐴) → 𝐴 = 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | pstr 17258 | A poset is transitive. (Contributed by NM, 12-May-2008.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 30-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 ∈ PosetRel ∧ 𝐴𝑅𝐵 ∧ 𝐵𝑅𝐶) → 𝐴𝑅𝐶) | ||
Theorem | cnvps 17259 | The converse of a poset is a poset. In the general case (◡𝑅 ∈ PosetRel → 𝑅 ∈ PosetRel) is not true. See cnvpsb 17260 for a special case where the property holds. (Contributed by FL, 5-Jan-2009.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 3-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑅 ∈ PosetRel → ◡𝑅 ∈ PosetRel) | ||
Theorem | cnvpsb 17260 | The converse of a poset is a poset. (Contributed by FL, 5-Jan-2009.) |
⊢ (Rel 𝑅 → (𝑅 ∈ PosetRel ↔ ◡𝑅 ∈ PosetRel)) | ||
Theorem | psss 17261 | Any subset of a partially ordered set is partially ordered. (Contributed by FL, 24-Jan-2010.) |
⊢ (𝑅 ∈ PosetRel → (𝑅 ∩ (𝐴 × 𝐴)) ∈ PosetRel) | ||
Theorem | psssdm2 17262 | Field of a subposet. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = dom 𝑅 ⇒ ⊢ (𝑅 ∈ PosetRel → dom (𝑅 ∩ (𝐴 × 𝐴)) = (𝑋 ∩ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | psssdm 17263 | Field of a subposet. (Contributed by FL, 19-Sep-2011.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 9-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = dom 𝑅 ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑅 ∈ PosetRel ∧ 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑋) → dom (𝑅 ∩ (𝐴 × 𝐴)) = 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | istsr 17264 | The predicate is a toset. (Contributed by FL, 1-Nov-2009.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 22-Nov-2013.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = dom 𝑅 ⇒ ⊢ (𝑅 ∈ TosetRel ↔ (𝑅 ∈ PosetRel ∧ (𝑋 × 𝑋) ⊆ (𝑅 ∪ ◡𝑅))) | ||
Theorem | istsr2 17265* | The predicate is a toset. (Contributed by FL, 1-Nov-2009.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 22-Nov-2013.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = dom 𝑅 ⇒ ⊢ (𝑅 ∈ TosetRel ↔ (𝑅 ∈ PosetRel ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝑋 (𝑥𝑅𝑦 ∨ 𝑦𝑅𝑥))) | ||
Theorem | tsrlin 17266 | A toset is a linear order. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = dom 𝑅 ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑅 ∈ TosetRel ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑋 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑋) → (𝐴𝑅𝐵 ∨ 𝐵𝑅𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | tsrlemax 17267 | Two ways of saying a number is less than or equal to the maximum of two others. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = dom 𝑅 ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑅 ∈ TosetRel ∧ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑋 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑋 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝑋)) → (𝐴𝑅if(𝐵𝑅𝐶, 𝐶, 𝐵) ↔ (𝐴𝑅𝐵 ∨ 𝐴𝑅𝐶))) | ||
Theorem | tsrps 17268 | A toset is a poset. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑅 ∈ TosetRel → 𝑅 ∈ PosetRel) | ||
Theorem | cnvtsr 17269 | The converse of a toset is a toset. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑅 ∈ TosetRel → ◡𝑅 ∈ TosetRel ) | ||
Theorem | tsrss 17270 | Any subset of a totally ordered set is totally ordered. (Contributed by FL, 24-Jan-2010.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 21-Nov-2013.) |
⊢ (𝑅 ∈ TosetRel → (𝑅 ∩ (𝐴 × 𝐴)) ∈ TosetRel ) | ||
Theorem | ledm 17271 | domain of ≤ is ℝ*. (Contributed by FL, 2-Aug-2009.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 4-May-2015.) |
⊢ ℝ* = dom ≤ | ||
Theorem | lern 17272 | The range of ≤ is ℝ*. (Contributed by FL, 2-Aug-2009.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ ℝ* = ran ≤ | ||
Theorem | lefld 17273 | The field of the 'less or equal to' relationship on the extended real. (Contributed by FL, 2-Aug-2009.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 4-May-2015.) |
⊢ ℝ* = ∪ ∪ ≤ | ||
Theorem | letsr 17274 | The "less than or equal to" relationship on the extended reals is a toset. (Contributed by FL, 2-Aug-2009.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ ≤ ∈ TosetRel | ||
Syntax | cdir 17275 | Extend class notation with the class of all directed sets. |
class DirRel | ||
Syntax | ctail 17276 | Extend class notation with the tail function. |
class tail | ||
Definition | df-dir 17277 | Define the class of all directed sets/directions. (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 25-Nov-2009.) |
⊢ DirRel = {𝑟 ∣ ((Rel 𝑟 ∧ ( I ↾ ∪ ∪ 𝑟) ⊆ 𝑟) ∧ ((𝑟 ∘ 𝑟) ⊆ 𝑟 ∧ (∪ ∪ 𝑟 × ∪ ∪ 𝑟) ⊆ (◡𝑟 ∘ 𝑟)))} | ||
Definition | df-tail 17278* | Define the tail function for directed sets. (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 25-Nov-2009.) |
⊢ tail = (𝑟 ∈ DirRel ↦ (𝑥 ∈ ∪ ∪ 𝑟 ↦ (𝑟 “ {𝑥}))) | ||
Theorem | isdir 17279 | A condition for a relation to be a direction. (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 25-Nov-2009.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 22-Nov-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐴 = ∪ ∪ 𝑅 ⇒ ⊢ (𝑅 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝑅 ∈ DirRel ↔ ((Rel 𝑅 ∧ ( I ↾ 𝐴) ⊆ 𝑅) ∧ ((𝑅 ∘ 𝑅) ⊆ 𝑅 ∧ (𝐴 × 𝐴) ⊆ (◡𝑅 ∘ 𝑅))))) | ||
Theorem | reldir 17280 | A direction is a relation. (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 25-Nov-2009.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 22-Nov-2013.) |
⊢ (𝑅 ∈ DirRel → Rel 𝑅) | ||
Theorem | dirdm 17281 | A direction's domain is equal to its field. (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 25-Nov-2009.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 22-Nov-2013.) |
⊢ (𝑅 ∈ DirRel → dom 𝑅 = ∪ ∪ 𝑅) | ||
Theorem | dirref 17282 | A direction is reflexive. (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 25-Nov-2009.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 22-Nov-2013.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = dom 𝑅 ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑅 ∈ DirRel ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑋) → 𝐴𝑅𝐴) | ||
Theorem | dirtr 17283 | A direction is transitive. (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 25-Nov-2009.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 22-Nov-2013.) |
⊢ (((𝑅 ∈ DirRel ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝑉) ∧ (𝐴𝑅𝐵 ∧ 𝐵𝑅𝐶)) → 𝐴𝑅𝐶) | ||
Theorem | dirge 17284* | For any two elements of a directed set, there exists a third element greater than or equal to both. (Note that this does not say that the two elements have a least upper bound.) (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 25-Nov-2009.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 22-Nov-2013.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = dom 𝑅 ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑅 ∈ DirRel ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑋 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑋) → ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 (𝐴𝑅𝑥 ∧ 𝐵𝑅𝑥)) | ||
Theorem | tsrdir 17285 | A totally ordered set is a directed set. (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 25-Nov-2009.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 22-Nov-2013.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ TosetRel → 𝐴 ∈ DirRel) | ||
According to Wikipedia ("Magma (algebra)", 08-Jan-2020, https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/magma_(algebra)) "In abstract algebra, a magma [...] is a basic kind of algebraic structure. Specifically, a magma consists of a set equipped with a single binary operation. The binary operation must be closed by definition but no other properties are imposed.". Since the concept of a "binary operation" is used in different variants, these differences are explained in more detail in the following: With df-mpt2 6695, binary operations are defined by a rule, and with df-ov 6693, the value of a binary operation applied to two operands can be expressed. In both cases, the two operands can belong to different sets, and the result can be an element of a third set. However, according to Wikipedia "Binary operation", see https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Binary_operation (19-Jan-2020), "... a binary operation on a set 𝑆 is a mapping of the elements of the Cartesian product 𝑆 × 𝑆 to S: 𝑓:𝑆 × 𝑆⟶𝑆. Because the result of performing the operation on a pair of elements of S is again an element of S, the operation is called a closed binary operation on S (or sometimes expressed as having the property of closure).". To distinguish this more restrictive definition (in Wikipedia and most of the literature) from the general case, binary operations mapping the elements of the Cartesian product 𝑆 × 𝑆 are more precisely called internal binary operations. If, in addition, the result is also contained in the set 𝑆, the operation should be called closed internal binary operation. Therefore, a "binary operation on a set 𝑆" according to Wikipedia is a "closed internal binary operation" in a more precise terminology. If the sets are different, the operation is explicitly called external binary operation (see Wikipedia https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Binary_operation#External_binary_operations ). The definition of magmas (Mgm, see df-mgm 17289) concentrates on the closure property of the associated operation, and poses no additional restrictions on it. In this way, it is most general and flexible. | ||
Syntax | cplusf 17286 | Extend class notation with group addition as a function. |
class +𝑓 | ||
Syntax | cmgm 17287 | Extend class notation with class of all magmas. |
class Mgm | ||
Definition | df-plusf 17288* | Define group addition function. Usually we will use +g directly instead of +𝑓, and they have the same behavior in most cases. The main advantage of +𝑓 for any magma is that it is a guaranteed function (mgmplusf 17298), while +g only has closure (mgmcl 17292). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 14-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ +𝑓 = (𝑔 ∈ V ↦ (𝑥 ∈ (Base‘𝑔), 𝑦 ∈ (Base‘𝑔) ↦ (𝑥(+g‘𝑔)𝑦))) | ||
Definition | df-mgm 17289* | A magma is a set equipped with an everywhere defined internal operation. Definition 1 in [BourbakiAlg1] p. 1, or definition of a groupoid in section I.1 of [Bruck] p. 1. Note: The term "groupoid" is now widely used to refer to other objects: (small) categories all of whose morphisms are invertible, or groups with a partial function replacing the binary operation. Therefore, we will only use the term "magma" for the present notion in set.mm. (Contributed by FL, 2-Nov-2009.) (Revised by AV, 6-Jan-2020.) |
⊢ Mgm = {𝑔 ∣ [(Base‘𝑔) / 𝑏][(+g‘𝑔) / 𝑜]∀𝑥 ∈ 𝑏 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝑏 (𝑥𝑜𝑦) ∈ 𝑏} | ||
Theorem | ismgm 17290* | The predicate "is a magma". (Contributed by FL, 2-Nov-2009.) (Revised by AV, 6-Jan-2020.) |
⊢ 𝐵 = (Base‘𝑀) & ⊢ ⚬ = (+g‘𝑀) ⇒ ⊢ (𝑀 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝑀 ∈ Mgm ↔ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 (𝑥 ⚬ 𝑦) ∈ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | ismgmn0 17291* | The predicate "is a magma" for a structure with a nonempty base set. (Contributed by AV, 29-Jan-2020.) |
⊢ 𝐵 = (Base‘𝑀) & ⊢ ⚬ = (+g‘𝑀) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 → (𝑀 ∈ Mgm ↔ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 (𝑥 ⚬ 𝑦) ∈ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | mgmcl 17292 | Closure of the operation of a magma. (Contributed by FL, 14-Sep-2010.) (Revised by AV, 13-Jan-2020.) |
⊢ 𝐵 = (Base‘𝑀) & ⊢ ⚬ = (+g‘𝑀) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑀 ∈ Mgm ∧ 𝑋 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝑌 ∈ 𝐵) → (𝑋 ⚬ 𝑌) ∈ 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | isnmgm 17293 | A condition for a structure not to be a magma. (Contributed by AV, 30-Jan-2020.) (Proof shortened by NM, 5-Feb-2020.) |
⊢ 𝐵 = (Base‘𝑀) & ⊢ ⚬ = (+g‘𝑀) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑋 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝑌 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ (𝑋 ⚬ 𝑌) ∉ 𝐵) → 𝑀 ∉ Mgm) | ||
Theorem | plusffval 17294* | The group addition operation as a function. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 14-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐵 = (Base‘𝐺) & ⊢ + = (+g‘𝐺) & ⊢ ⨣ = (+𝑓‘𝐺) ⇒ ⊢ ⨣ = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐵, 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ (𝑥 + 𝑦)) | ||
Theorem | plusfval 17295 | The group addition operation as a function. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 14-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐵 = (Base‘𝐺) & ⊢ + = (+g‘𝐺) & ⊢ ⨣ = (+𝑓‘𝐺) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑋 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝑌 ∈ 𝐵) → (𝑋 ⨣ 𝑌) = (𝑋 + 𝑌)) | ||
Theorem | plusfeq 17296 | If the addition operation is already a function, the functionalization of it is equal to the original operation. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 14-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐵 = (Base‘𝐺) & ⊢ + = (+g‘𝐺) & ⊢ ⨣ = (+𝑓‘𝐺) ⇒ ⊢ ( + Fn (𝐵 × 𝐵) → ⨣ = + ) | ||
Theorem | plusffn 17297 | The group addition operation is a function. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 20-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐵 = (Base‘𝐺) & ⊢ ⨣ = (+𝑓‘𝐺) ⇒ ⊢ ⨣ Fn (𝐵 × 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | mgmplusf 17298 | The group addition function of a magma is a function into its base set. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 14-Aug-2015.) (Revisd by AV, 28-Jan-2020.) |
⊢ 𝐵 = (Base‘𝑀) & ⊢ ⨣ = (+𝑓‘𝑀) ⇒ ⊢ (𝑀 ∈ Mgm → ⨣ :(𝐵 × 𝐵)⟶𝐵) | ||
Theorem | issstrmgm 17299* | Characterize a substructure as submagma by closure properties. (Contributed by AV, 30-Aug-2021.) |
⊢ 𝐵 = (Base‘𝐺) & ⊢ + = (+g‘𝐺) & ⊢ 𝐻 = (𝐺 ↾s 𝑆) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐻 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝑆 ⊆ 𝐵) → (𝐻 ∈ Mgm ↔ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝑆 (𝑥 + 𝑦) ∈ 𝑆)) | ||
Theorem | intopsn 17300 | The internal operation for a set is the trivial operation iff the set is a singleton. Formerly part of proof of ring1zr 19323. (Contributed by FL, 13-Feb-2010.) (Revised by AV, 23-Jan-2020.) |
⊢ (( ⚬ :(𝐵 × 𝐵)⟶𝐵 ∧ 𝑍 ∈ 𝐵) → (𝐵 = {𝑍} ↔ ⚬ = {〈〈𝑍, 𝑍〉, 𝑍〉})) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |